User Tools

Site Tools


theories

Link to this comparison view

Both sides previous revision Previous revision
Next revision
Previous revision
theories [2018/05/06 10:33]
jakobadmin [Overview]
theories [2020/04/09 20:35] (current)
68.142.63.195 [Overview] Removed sexist material
Line 13: Line 13:
 | | ,| -| AA |-|.|AA=[[theories:​speculative_theories:​quantum_gravity|Quantum Gravity]] | | ,| -| AA |-|.|AA=[[theories:​speculative_theories:​quantum_gravity|Quantum Gravity]]
 | |!@4| | | ||| !@4 | | | |!@4| | | ||| !@4 | |
-| BB | |||  CC |  | |BB=[[theories:​quantum_field_theory|Quantum Field Theory]]|CC=[[theories:​general_relativity|General Relativity]]+| BB | |||  CC |  | |BB=[[theories:​quantum_field_theory|Quantum Field Theory]]|CC=[[models:​general_relativity|General Relativity]]
 | |!@4| | | ||| !@4 | | | |!@4| | | ||| !@4 | |
-| DD| |||  EE |  | |DD=[[theories:​quantum_mechanics|Quantum Mechanics]]|EE=[[theories:​special_relativity|Special Relativity]]+| DD| |||  EE |  | |DD=[[theories:​quantum_mechanics|Quantum Mechanics]]|EE=[[models:​special_relativity|Special Relativity]]
 |  || | | ||| !@4 | | |  || | | ||| !@4 | |
 | | || |||  FF |  | |FF=[[theories:​classical_mechanics|Classical Mechanics]] | | || |||  FF |  | |FF=[[theories:​classical_mechanics|Classical Mechanics]]
Line 23: Line 23:
  
 [[theories:​classical_mechanics|Classical mechanics]] describes everyday physics and can be described by using everyday space, configuration space, phase space or Hilbert space((See the discussion at [[theories:​classical_mechanics|classical mechanics]])). Classical mechanics works perfectly for phenomena like billiard-ball collisions. However, we can ask what happens if we make the billiard balls smaller and smaller? What if we scale the whole system down by a factor 10, a factor 1000, or even a factor 10000? Will the laws of classical mechanics still hold?  [[theories:​classical_mechanics|Classical mechanics]] describes everyday physics and can be described by using everyday space, configuration space, phase space or Hilbert space((See the discussion at [[theories:​classical_mechanics|classical mechanics]])). Classical mechanics works perfectly for phenomena like billiard-ball collisions. However, we can ask what happens if we make the billiard balls smaller and smaller? What if we scale the whole system down by a factor 10, a factor 1000, or even a factor 10000? Will the laws of classical mechanics still hold? 
 +
 +{{ :​theoriesoverviewbyscale.png?​nolink&​400|}}
  
 In principle this could be since the $m$ in [[equations:​newtons_second_law|Newton'​s second law]] does not come with a predefined allowed mass range, say 0.1 kg up to 10000 kg. But the correct answer is no. If we make things smaller and smaller we eventually end up in a regime where the laws of classical mechanics no longer apply. The scale where this happens is encoded in Planck'​s constant $\hbar$. If we are dealing with systems where the [[formalisms:​lagrangian_formalism|action]] is much larger than $\hbar$ we can treat it using classical mechanics. Effectively this means that we set $\hbar$ to zero. If the action of the system is close to $\hbar$ we need to take quantum effects into account.  ​ In principle this could be since the $m$ in [[equations:​newtons_second_law|Newton'​s second law]] does not come with a predefined allowed mass range, say 0.1 kg up to 10000 kg. But the correct answer is no. If we make things smaller and smaller we eventually end up in a regime where the laws of classical mechanics no longer apply. The scale where this happens is encoded in Planck'​s constant $\hbar$. If we are dealing with systems where the [[formalisms:​lagrangian_formalism|action]] is much larger than $\hbar$ we can treat it using classical mechanics. Effectively this means that we set $\hbar$ to zero. If the action of the system is close to $\hbar$ we need to take quantum effects into account.  ​
  
-{{ :​paper.journal.6.png?​nolink&​400|}} 
  
-The crucial difference between classical and quantum mechanics is that the algebra for observables is non-commutative,​ as encoded in [[advanced_notions:​uncertainty_principle|Heisenberg'​s uncertainty principle]]((In words the non-commutativity,​ it makes a tiny difference ($sim \hbar$) whether we first measure the momentum or the location of a particle)). Apart from this difference, we can again use everyday space, configuration space, phase space or Hilbert space((See the discussion at [[theories:​quantum_mechanics|quantum mechanics]])). ​ 
  
-Another instance where classical mechanics ​becomes invalid ​is when our objects move at speeds close to the speed of light $c$. In such systemsthe correct theory is [[theories:special_relativity|special relativity]]. The difference ​between special relativity and classical mechanics is that we now use Minkowski space instead ​of our everyday Euclidean spaceAgain we can equivalently ​use the corresponding ​configuration space, phase space or Hilbert space.  When the objects in our system move so slowly that we can treat effectively $c$ as infinity, we can use classical ​mechanics+The crucial difference between ​classical ​and quantum ​mechanics is that the algebra for observables is non-commutativeas encoded in [[advanced_notions:uncertainty_principle|Heisenberg'​s uncertainty principle]]((In words the non-commutativity,​ it makes a tiny difference ​($sim \hbar$) whether ​we first measure the momentum or the location ​of a particle))Apart from this difference, ​we can again use everyday space, ​configuration space, phase space or Hilbert space((See the discussion at [[theories:​quantum_mechanics|quantum mechanics]])). The question why we need to change ​our "​naive"​ algebra to a non-commutative one is the what discussions about the [[https://​physicstravelguide.com/​theories/​quantum_mechanics#​tab__interpretations|interpretation of quantum mechanics are all about]]. The procedure where we start with a classical ​theory an construct the corresponding quantum theory is known as [[advanced_tools:​quantization|quantization]]
  
-Next, when we are dealing with tiny objects that move at speeds close to the speed of light, both, quantum mechanics and special relativity, fail. If we combine the lessons learned in quantum mechanics and special relativity properly we end up with [[theories:​quantum_field_theory|quantum field theory]]. Here the fields obey a non-commutative algebra and it is conventional to describe quantum fields either in Hilbert space or configuration space((see the discussion at [[theories:​quantum_field_theory|quantum field theory]])). The Hilbert or configuration space in //​interacting//​ quantum field theory is more complicated since the particles described by quantum fields can have an internal structure and this internal structure becomes important when fields interact((Examples,​ for internal structure are [[advanced_tools:​gauge_symmetry|gauge symmetry]] and [[basic_notions:​spin|spin]]. For example, for spin $1/2$ particles the internal space is $\mathbb{C}^2$. For [[advanced_tools:​group_theory:​u1|$U(1)$]] gauge symmetry we get a copy of the unit circle $S^1$ (since $U(1)\simeq S^1$) above each spacetime point.)). Hence our physics not only happens in spacetime but also in internal spaces. The theory that deals with physics in internal space is known as [[theories:​gauge_theory|gauge theory]]. The appropriate geometrical tool to describe physics in spacetime and internal spaces at the same time are [[advanced_tools:​fiber_bundles|fiber bundles]]. ​ 
  
-A third instance where classical mechanics fails is in systems where gravity is strong((For example, in the neighborhood of large stars or [[advanced_notions:​black_hole|black holes]])). In such systems, the correct theory is Einstein'​s [[theories:​general_relativity|general relativity]]. Here the Minkowski space of special relativity becomes replaced with a more general Lorentzian manifold. Hence spacetime only looks locally like Minkowksi space and is otherwise curved.  ​+ 
 +Another instance where classical mechanics becomes invalid is when our objects move at speeds close to the speed of light $c$. In such systems, the correct theory is [[models:​special_relativity|special relativity]]. The difference between special relativity and classical mechanics is that we now use Minkowski space instead of our everyday Euclidean space. Again we can equivalently use the corresponding configuration space, phase space or a Hilbert space. ​ When the objects in our system move so slowly that we can treat effectively $c$ as infinity, we can use classical mechanics.  
 + 
 +{{:​paper.journal.6.png?​nolink&​400 |}} 
 +Next, when we are dealing with tiny objects that move at speeds close to the speed of light, both, quantum mechanics and special relativity, fail. If we combine the lessons learned in quantum mechanics and special relativity properly we end up with [[theories:​quantum_field_theory|quantum field theory]]. Here the fields obey a non-commutative algebra and it is conventional to describe quantum fields either in Hilbert space or configuration space((see the discussion at [[theories:​quantum_field_theory|quantum field theory]])). The Hilbert or configuration space in //​interacting//​ quantum field theory is more complicated since the particles described by quantum fields can have an internal structure and this internal structure becomes important when fields interact((Examples,​ for internal structure are [[advanced_tools:​gauge_symmetry|gauge symmetry]] and [[basic_notions:​spin|spin]]. For example, for spin $1/2$ particles the internal space is $\mathbb{C}^2$. For [[advanced_tools:​group_theory:​u1|$U(1)$]] gauge symmetry we get a copy of the unit circle $S^1$ (since $U(1)\simeq S^1$) above each spacetime point.)). Hence our physics not only happens in spacetime but also in internal spaces. The theory that deals with physics in internal space is known as [[models:​gauge_theory|gauge theory]]. The appropriate geometrical tool to describe physics in spacetime and internal spaces at the same time are [[advanced_tools:​fiber_bundles|fiber bundles]].  
 + 
 +A third instance where classical mechanics fails is in systems where gravity is strong((For example, in the neighborhood of large stars or [[advanced_notions:​black_hole|black holes]])). In such systems, the correct theory is Einstein'​s [[models:​general_relativity|general relativity]]. Here the Minkowski space of special relativity becomes replaced with a more general Lorentzian manifold. Hence spacetime only looks locally like Minkowksi space and is otherwise curved.  ​
  
 So far, there is no theory that works for systems with strong gravity and tiny objects that move close to the speed of light. The //​hypothetical//​ theory that combines the lessons of general relativity and quantum field theory is known as [[theories:​speculative_theories:​quantum_gravity|quantum gravity]]. ​ So far, there is no theory that works for systems with strong gravity and tiny objects that move close to the speed of light. The //​hypothetical//​ theory that combines the lessons of general relativity and quantum field theory is known as [[theories:​speculative_theories:​quantum_gravity|quantum gravity]]. ​
Line 47: Line 52:
 <-- <--
  
----- +<​tabbox ​Field Theories vs. Particle Theories>
- +
-**Classical Theories vs. Quantum Theories** +
- +
-The difference between a quantum and a classical theory is which algebra we use for the observables. The question why we need to change our "​naive"​ algebra to a non-commutative one is the what discussions about the [[https://​physicstravelguide.com/​theories/​quantum_mechanics#​tab__interpretations|interpretation of quantum mechanics are all about]]. The procedure where we start with a classical theory an construct the corresponding quantum theory is known as [[advanced_tools:​quantization|quantization]].  +
- +
----- +
- +
-**Field Theories vs. Particle Theories**+
  
 In a particle theory, the solutions describe __particle trajectories__:​ In a particle theory, the solutions describe __particle trajectories__:​
Line 65: Line 62:
 {{ :​fieldsequence2.png?​nolink&​600 |}} {{ :​fieldsequence2.png?​nolink&​600 |}}
  
 +However, take note that we can also describe particles in field theory. A particle in quantum field theory is interpreted as a field excitation. When, for example, every electron is an excitation of the same electron field, we can undertand why every electron that we observed so far looked exactly the same.
  
-Field theories have the big advantage that they treat time and space on an equal footing, which is necessary because of special relativity.+Field theories have the further ​big advantage that they treat time and space on an equal footing, which is necessary because of special relativity. ​In contrast, in a particle theory, we always use the location as a function of time $q=q(t)$ to describe the particles in question. A field $\Phi$ is a function of space and time $\Phi(x,​t)$. 
 + 
 +Another advantage is that field theories are much better suited if we are dealing with systems where particles disappear and different particle appear instead since we can use the field as a bookkeeping device. Formulated differently,​ a field is a much better tool to keep track of particle appearances and disappearances than a description in terms of individual trajectories.  
 + 
 +Despite all this, the question remains: What is more fundamental,​ particles or fields? 
 + 
 +If we look close enough our detectors always see particles and not fields. Hence some people((c.f. Nima Arkani-Hamed et. al.)) argue that only particles are real and fields are merely convenient calculation devices, similar to the wave function in quantum mechanics((Moreover,​ every time we took the quantum field idea seriously we ended up with horribly wrong predictions:​ the [[open_problems:​strong_cp_puzzle|strong CP problem]], the monopole problem,​...)).  
 + 
 +In the conventional interpretation,​ charged particles are sources for fields. However, it is also possible to imagine that fields are the sources of particles((This is known as "​charge without charge"​. See also the discussion in section 15 in the book "​Gravitation"​ by Misner, Thorne, and Wheeler)). Namely, when there is a wormhole in spacetime the field lines flowing in and out of the wormhole look like those of a particle-antiparticle pair. 
 + 
 +<WRAP group> 
 +<WRAP half column>​ 
 +{{ ::​wormholecharge.png?​nolink&​400 |}} 
 +</​WRAP>​ 
 + 
 +<WRAP half column>​ 
 +{{ :​normalcharge.png?​nolink&​400 |}} 
 +</​WRAP>​ 
 +</​WRAP>​ 
 +<​blockquote>​One view: Source is primary. Field may have other duties, but its prime duty is 
 +to serve as "​slave"​ of source. Conservation of source comes first; field has to adjust 
 +itself accordingly. 
 +Alternative view: Field is primary. Field takes the responsibility of seeing to it 
 +that the source obeys the conservation law. Source would not know what to do in 
 +absence of the field, and would not even exist. Source is "​built"​ from field. Conservation of source is consequence of this construction. One model illustrating this view in an elementary context: Concept of "​classical"​ 
 +electric charge as nothing but "​electric lines of force trapped in the topology of a 
 +multiply connected space" [Weyl (1924b); Wheeler (1955); Misner and Wheeler 
 +(1957)]. 
 +On any view: Integral of source density-current over any three-dimensional region 
 +(a "​cube"​ in simplified analysis above) equals integral of field over boundary of 
 +this region (the six faces of the cube above). No one has ever found any other way 
 +to understand the correlation between field law and conservation law. 
 +<​cite>​section 15 in the book "​Gravitation"​ by Misner, Thorne, and Wheeler</​cite></​blockquote>​
  
-In contrast, in a particle theory, we always use the location as a function of time $q=q(t)$ to describe the particles in question. A field $\Phi$ is a function of space and time $\Phi(x,​t)$. 
  
-Field theories are much better suited if we are dealing with systems where particles disappear and different particle appear instead. 
-Formulated differently,​ a field is a much better tool to keep track of particle appearances and disappearances than a description in terms of individual trajectories. ​ 
  
 ---- ----
theories.1525595590.txt.gz · Last modified: 2018/05/06 08:33 (external edit)